am not scared of much in the way of illness and death (I tell myself) but I am scared of dementia and blindness. These are an intellectual’s fears: being unable to think and unable to read. There’s braille, yes, but that’s different from being able to see words and letters; it’s different, that is, to someone for whom reading has always been a form of seeing rather than touching. I suppose that’s also an intellectual’s distinction—possibly a curmudgeon’s too. Mainly the fear has to do with adjusting to a world that is less. “Something in the sight / Adjusts itself to midnight,” Emily Dickinson writes. But there is resignation and sadness, not consolation, in that. Milton, perhaps, has a healthier philosophy of blindness.
Doth God exact day-labour, light deny’d,
I fondly ask; But patience to prevent
That murmur, soon replies, God doth not need
Either man’s work or his own gifts, who best
Bear his milde yoak, they serve him best.
This is healthier largely because it has the virtue of undeluded honesty. When Milton is tempted to complain that God can hardly ask him to work unaided by his sight, his “patience” reminds him that God has no need of John Milton or his work, and that “best” service lies in accepting the “milde yoak” God has given us. It is a stark lesson, and I wonder greatly whether I’d have the same patience for it as John Milton. Even though my eyes and my mind and all I have belong to God, I confess I am attached. Neither Milton nor Dickinson explains why God, as it seems, chooses to play games with people’s sight. He gives it to some; withholds it from others; removes it from some who’ve had it; grants it to others formerly blind. Probably we should reflect that our capacities belong to God, not to ourselves. The Lord giveth and the Lord taketh away. But it seems a rather arbitrary method of making the point. Why this person and not that? Because none can answer such a question, I am content to pose it and then leave it alone. In its place, I would consider the experiences, not of those who have lost their sight, but those who have had it restored.
Agnosia & fear.
Annie Dillard has written what I take to be the best meditation on blindness and sight in the second chapter of her Pulitzer Prize-winning classic Pilgrim at Tinker Creek. The chapter is titled “Seeing.” In it she tells the stories of several men and women, blinded by cataracts since birth, who were among the first to receive their sight after physicians learned how to perform surgery on such people. If their experiences are any indication, receiving one’s sight after a lifetime of blindness may be more curse than blessing. The difficulty involves spatial perception, depth perception, and the ability to identify and give meaning to what the world presents to the eyes. Dillard explains:
Before the operation a doctor would give a blind patient a cube and a sphere; the patient would tongue it or feel it with his hands, and name it correctly. After the operation a doctor would show the same objects to the patient without letting him touch them; now he had no clue whatsoever what he was seeing. One patient called lemonade ‘square’ because it pricked on his tongue as a square shape pricked on the touch of his hands. (27–28)
Maurice von Senden, whose 1932 book Space and Sight is Dillard’s source, describes another case.
Those who are blind from birth … have no real conception of height or distance. A house that is a mile away is thought of as nearby, but requiring the taking of a lot of steps. … The elevator that whizzes him up and down gives no more sense of vertical distance than the train does of horizontal. (Dillard qtg. von Senden 28)
In one case a patient sees a painting after her operation; she asks why there are “those dark marks all over them.” Her mother tells her they are shadows; she says if it weren’t for a painting’s representation of shadows, everything would look flat. “Well, that’s how they do look,” she says. “Everything looks flat with dull patches.” Dillard describes this as “pure sensation unencumbered by meaning.” It is “a dazzle of color patches.” The patients, she says, “are pleased by the sensation of color, and quickly learn to name the colors, but the rest of seeing is tormentingly difficult” (28–29).
It all sounds very distressing and disorienting—to suddenly be able to see but not know what anything is; or to have the world look all askew. We call it agnosia—the inability to make sense of what one is able to see; and it is common among those who have been blind from birth, or who went blind at an early age but have had their sight restored. Whatever else you might call the experience, it doesn’t sound like a blessing. Not really. For at some point in the experience of the unblind—too early for anyone to remember—we learn to interpret what the eyes present to us. We learn to identify objects. We learn, for example, to differentiate objects from the shadows they cast and to see in three dimensions; to interpret the size of an object, the shape of an object, the distance of an object. We learn the difference between vertical and horizontal space. But the blind have never had occasion to learn such things; their other senses—taste, touch, smell—are their only means of encounter with the world. Thus for those who regain their sight, there is no interpretive filter. They can see; they cannot perceive.
We also know the phonemonenon as Molyneux’s Problem, after the eighteenth-century philosopher William Molyneux, who posed the question to John Locke in the form of a thought experiment. It was because of his hypothesis that the physicians performed the experiment with the cube and the sphere. Molyneux explains:
Suppose a man born blind, and now adult, and taught by his touch to distinguish between a cube and a sphere of the same metal, and nighly of the same bigness, so as to tell, when he felt one and other, which is the cube, which is the sphere. Suppose then the cube and the sphere placed on a table, and the blind man made to see: query, Whether by his sight, before he touched them, he could now distinguish which is the globe, which the cube? To which the acute and judicious proposer answers: Not. For though he has obtained the experience of how a globe, and how a cube, affects his touch; yet he has not obtained the experience, that what affects his touch so or so, must affect his sight so or so.
We know today that Molyneux was right. Sight and perception are not the same thing; God gives us sight, but perception we must learn. Vision for the newly-sighted is “pure sensation unencumbered by meaning”; meaning we must achieve. And that can be, in Dillard’s words, “tormentingly difficult” and “overwhelming.” As a result, many of the patients in von Senden’s study refused to use their sight; shut their eyes; and relapsed into their former state. “No, really,” one cried, “I can’t stand it anymore; I want to be sent back to the asylum again. If things aren’t altered, I’ll tear my eyes out.” Others, who learned to adjust, nevertheless lost the self-peace they once had and became quickly ashamed of what sort of impression they were making on others. One began to suffer obsessive-compulsive disorder about his physical appearance (30).
Color patches & wonder.
These are indeed unhappy stories that should make anyone feel rather pity than rejoicing. Take a person who has already learned to interpret the world through the senses he does have; restore to him his sight, under the guise of a great blessing and joy; and thus subject him to the distressing reality of agnosia, so that he now understands nothing, and is disoriented by what the world presents to him, and longs to return to his blindness. Well, what was God up to when he healed all those blind people? But in a paragraph that is worth quoting in full, Dillard shows us the other side of the experience. “Many newly-sighted people,” she writes,
speak well of the world and teach us how dull is our own vision. To one patient, a human hand, unrecognized, is “something bright and then holes.” Shown a bunch of grapes, a boy cries out, “It is dark, blue, and shiny. … It isn’t smooth, it has bumps and hollows.” A little girl visits a garden. “She is greatly astonished, and can scarcely be persuaded to answer, stands speechless in front of the tree, which she only names on taking hold of it, and then as “the tree with the lights in it.”
So agnosia can cause fear and terror. But it can also be a source of wonder, of seeing things in a fresh and unexpected way in much the same way an artist sees. It could be that the difference lies in how the individual is constituted. Do we need definitions and certainties or do we crave a more visionary experience? Are we Newton or Van Gogh? Dillard herself envies the experience of “pure sensation unencumbered by meaning” and “a dazzle of color-patches.” She notes that, after reading von Senden, she “saw color-patches for weeks” (31); and she describes at length her effort to find “the tree with the lights in it” as seen by the little girl in the garden.
But she is distressed to find that she cannot “unpeach the peaches.” The meaning—the very identity—she assigns things interferes with her ability to see them “purely.” She longs for “the world unraveled from reason,” “Eden before Adam gave names” (32). Her almost inescapable reflex, however, is to see and then immediately “maintain … a running description,” even though all she wants to do is “gag the commentator, to hush the noise of useless interior babble” (33, 34).
The effort is really a discipline,” she says,
requiring a lifetime of dedicated struggle; it marks the literature of saints and monks of every order East and West, under every rule and no rule, discalced and shod. The world’s spiritual geniuses seem to discover universally that the mind’s muddy river, this ceaseless flow of trivia and trash, cannot be dammed, and that trying to dam it is a waste of effort that might lead to madness. … The act of seeing, then, is the pearl of great price. If I thought he could teach me to find it and keep it forever, I would stagger barefoot across a hundred deserts after any lunatic at all. But although the pearl may be found, it may not be sought. The literature of illumination reveals this above all: although it comes to those who wait for it, it is always, even to the most practiced and adept, a gift and a total surprise. (34–35)
Dillard does finally—in a thoughtless, unexpected moment—see the tree with the lights in it, “each cell buzzing with flame.” She says it was “less like seeing than like being for the first time seen.” It was as though she was a bell that had, for the first time, “been lifted and struck.” “I have since,” she concludes, “only very rarely seen the tree with the lights in it. The vision comes and goes, mostly goes, but I live for it” (36).
To stagger barefoot across a hundred deserts.
The old question: Which is better, reason or revelation? Or is this another nonsense question—a false dichotomy? To understand a vision at all, you somehow need to be able to name it, unless you’re content to be a babbling monster. If it seems mean to retreat from ecstasy for the sake of reason, isn’t it rather intolerable to consider a state of ecstasy that does not abate? How long can we sustain the vision without going mad? G.K. Chesterton insists that it is reason, not vision, that drives one mad. Chess players go mad, he says in Orthodoxy, but not poets (10–11). That’s not entirely true, and even Chesterton had to come down from the vision for the sake of analysis. So did Annie Dillard.
But I discover, in Dillard’s stories of the blind who gain their sight—both those whose experience of it is fear and those whose is ecstasy—a lesson about the experience of artists and visionaries, and what it means to say you see. Those who were blind knew they were missing something truly important to the experience of being fully alive; and to them nearly all depended on it. And so they took all the risks they did for the sake of seeing, whether their experience of sight, in the end, destroyed their peace or gave them incredible joy. They knew it was worth the risk. Dillard has the sensibility of an artist who would “stagger barefoot across a hundred deserts” for the sake of having the vision and never losing it.
How many of us who say we see instead walk through life and miss everything? How many come to the Eucharist—and I’ve seen this—and walk straightway out of Mass with Christ in their mouth and still chewing? Do they see the God who died for them? I’m comparing the experience of the blinded who see to the experience of artists and visionaries; and the reason we need them—both of them—is, in Dillard’s words, “to teach us how dull is our vision.” Artists, whether painter or poet, writer or sculptor or musician, show us the created world in unusual and startling ways. Through them we learn to see, though we’ve always had eyes. They shows us what we’ve missed. They wake us up. Who can read a description of grapes or trees, like that of the newly-sighted quoted by Dillard, and ever look at grapes or trees the same way again? And yet we have seen our whole lives and they’ve had their eyes for five minutes. Who is really blind? The heavens declare the glory of God, but I know I’ve shut my eyes to the heavens.
The vision does come at tremendous cost. Wordsworth complained in his Intimations ode that the “visionary gleam” had passed away. He remained sane—for a remarkably long life too—but his later poetry is a notorious disappointment. Van Gogh gave his sanity for the sake of retaining the vision. And who can look at a Van Gogh painting and see trees or fields the same way ever again? Can one see God and live? Van Gogh killed himself.
The god who spits.
Blind men, artists, and visionaries: For them, the ability to see matters a great deal. God, who is inscrutible, does not cooperate or deal with them in a manner that makes much sense. At least, it does not make much sense to our feeble reason, which understands less than we should like. In one of the swiftest and breeziest healings in all of scripture (but we’re talking about St. Mark, who regards all detail as superfluous) Christ restores sight to a blind man in the course of four clipped verses.
And he cometh to Bethsaida; and they bring a blind man unto him, and besought him to touch him. And he took the blind man by the hand, and led him out of town; and when he had spit on his eyes, he asked him if he saw ought. And he looked up, and said, I see men as trees, walking. After that he put his hands again upon his eyes, and made him look up: and he was restored, and saw every man clearly. (Mark 8:22–25)
As simple as that, I guess. St. Mark’s account is so brief we are apt to gloss it over and miss too much. But here we have Jesus behaving in a near-maniacal and quite unaccountable fashion. Being God, Christ could have healed the blind man with a wave of his hand. Instead, he makes a sacrament out of his saliva and spits in the man’s eyes. That strikes me as extreme. The poor man is looking for his sight back, and God acts like an anti-war protestor encountering a Vietnam vet. We want God to make sense and treat us with sympathy; and instead we get spit on.
When faced with such a passage, John Calvin has the standard response. Why did Christ spit in the blind man’s eyes? “Most probably,” he says, “for the purpose of proving … he had full liberty as to his method of proceeding, and was not resisted to a fixed rule.” So Jesus spits to prove a point about God’s sovereignty. Such exegesis makes it certain I shall not turn Calvinist any time soon.
Beyond that, however, I find in my review of the exegetical literature on this passage a curious—but almost universal—notion, which is that somehow Christ needs to heal the blind man twice, or in stages. Just to spit is not enough. This idea comes from the blind man’s words, “I see men as trees walking,” which seems to suggest a blurriness of vision. So the exegetes stumble all over themselves—blindly, as it were—to explain. The twelfth-century Orthodox archbishop Theophylact says that the blind man only had partial faith, so at first Christ heals him only partially. (This though Mark tells us nothing about the blind man’s faith.) For Favell Lee Mortimer, God is trying to illustrate a larger truth about how our spiritual blindness is only gradually cast off. Bishop George Witham, quoted in Haydock’s Bible Commentary of 1859, finds in the blind man’s words a lesson about “how difficult is a sinner’s conversion”—though the state of the blind man’s sinfulness is not described by Mark either. (Good luck with trying to find such details in Mark.) In the 2011 edition of the New American Bible, a footnote says: “Some commentators regard the [gradual] cure as an intended symbol of the gradual enlightenment of the disciples regarding Jesus’s messiahship.” Protestant commentator John Gill similarly draws the lesson that the Gospel truth is revealed to us gradually and in stages.
All of these generic points are true enough, as far as they go. (Though Calvin’s god seems a pretty insecure deity who even needs to spit to prove his sovereignty.) The problem is, I don’t think we need to draw grand spiritual lessons from the blind man’s words. A review of the medical literature would seem to suggest that the blind man has agnosia. He is fully capable of seeing—Christ gave him his sight—but he cannot identify what things are. So he sees men but they appear to be “as trees.” What Christ does in verse 25, in laying his hands upon him another time, is not to heal him again, or more perfectly, but to allow him to bypass the normal adjustment period. Far from being a lesson in imperfect faith, Christ gives the blind man a special grace.
Which becomes the real question: Is he? If we believe the happier stories in von Senden—if Annie Dillard’s longing for the tree with the lights in it, her hunger to always return to the vision, is valuable as an experience in its own right—then why couldn’t Christ have let the blind man experience a little longer the joy of seeing men as trees walking? Or did Christ, being of perfect knowledge, know that he would have been destroyed by it, like the others whom Dillard and von Senden describe? Mark does not say.
I know this much: I have seen the tree with the lights in it. I have seen men as trees walking. (That’s a later post.) And I would, like Dillard, stagger barefoot across a hundred deserts to be able to have the vision and keep it forever. So I’m inclined to say: Couldn’t Christ have let the blind man enjoy it for a while longer? Just a while? I should rejoice in the healing power of Christ, but I get to the end of the story and am a bit disappointed.
But if I am to draw any conclusion, I cannot go too far beyond the observation that seeing—like the word of God itself—is sharper than any two-edged sword; and it can lead to both despair and ecstasy; and ultimately God holds our seeing (like everything else) in the palm of his hand. That may be why I am so afraid to lose it. I don’t really object to Calvin’s insistence on the sovereignty of God to do as he pleases, to take our sight from us or give it back to us as he thinks best. Even if it requires spit. What I do object to is the notion that everything God does is specifically for the purpose of illustrating his sovereignty, and that mankind is nothing more than a puppet show to that end. God makes us for another purpose; God does with us what he will, for the sake of that other purpose. His sovereignty is the means but not the end.
I read the Gospels and I see: Christ heals the blind a lot. Human experience, and our capacity to know and to understand (and to reveal to others), depends upon our eyes. Seeing—or the lack of it—is very important not only in the fullness of our lives but in our capacity to know God and the world he has given us. But through the interplay of blindness and sight, the Almighty has his own purposes. Ours it not to reason why but sometimes just to reason.
And some days I can be unreasonably attached to my reason.
And other days I want to see men as trees, walking.
Discover more from To Give a Defense
Subscribe to get the latest posts sent to your email.